1887
Volume 13, Issue 1
  • ISSN 2211-4742
  • E-ISSN: 2211-4750
USD
Buy:$35.00 + Taxes

Abstract

Abstract

Linguistic arguments are paramount in legal interpretation. They are widely used by judges and considered to be ubiquitous across jurisdictions. It is claimed that they are decisive and limitative in the judicial interpretation of the law. The claims have long been subject to theoretical scrutiny and, recently, testing within experimental jurisprudence. In this paper, we analyse the judicial reasoning in a landmark Italian case from the end of the nineteenth century concerning Lidia Poët, an aspiring practising female lawyer. The case was decided in the last instance by the Turin Court of Cassation. We give a detailed argumentative analysis of the reasoning of the Court of Cassation in Turin in the Lidia Poët case and show that the crucial linguistic and systematic arguments used are not grounds for the interpretative decision to exclude women from the denotation of the word “lawyer.” We conclude that the linguistic arguments employed by courts often do not do the argumentative work they are expected to do. Instead, they cover the substantial views that have determined the ascription of normative meaning to a term or sentence.

Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.1075/jaic.00025.isi
2024-05-17
2025-04-29
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

References

  1. Alpa, Guido
    2010L’ingresso delle Donne nella Professione Legali. Rassegna Forense21: 223–244.
    [Google Scholar]
  2. Altavilla, Enrico
    1955Psicologia Giudiziaria, II Gli Attori del Procedimento Penale. Torino: Unione Tipografico-Editrice Torinese, IV edizione.
    [Google Scholar]
  3. Alvarez, Maria
    2017 “Reasons for Action: Justification, Motivation, Explanation.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. byEdward N. Zalta.
    [Google Scholar]
  4. Baude, William & Doerfler, Ryan D.
    2017 “The (Not So) Plain Meaning Rule.” The University of Chicago Law Review84(2):539–566.
    [Google Scholar]
  5. Bianchi, Antonio
    1886Sull’esercizio delle professioni di avvocato e di procuratore. Testo e commento della legge 8/06 1874 n. 1938, Serie 2, e del regolamento 26 luglio 1874, n. 2012 con appendice sugli onorari per l’avvocatura. Torino: Unione Tipografico Editrice.
    [Google Scholar]
  6. Borg, Emma
    2012 “Semantics without pragmatics?” The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. byKeith Allan & Kasia M. Jaszczolt. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9781139022453.028
    https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022453.028 [Google Scholar]
  7. Canale, Damiano & Tuzet, Giovanni
    2007 “On Legal Inferentialism. Toward a Pragmatics of Semantic Content in Legal Interpretation?” Ratio Juris20(1):32–44. 10.1111/j.1467‑9337.2007.00345.x
    https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2007.00345.x [Google Scholar]
  8. 2009 “The A Simili Argument: An Inferentialist Setting.” Ratio Juris22(4):499–509. 10.1111/j.1467‑9337.2009.00437.x
    https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2009.00437.x [Google Scholar]
  9. 2010 “What is the Reason for This Rule? An Inferential Account of the Ratio Legis.” Argumentation24(2):197–210. 10.1007/s10503‑009‑9171‑x
    https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-009-9171-x [Google Scholar]
  10. 2020 “What Is Legal Reasoning About: A Jurisprudential Account.” Economics in Legal Reasoning, ed. byFabrizio Esposito and Péter Cserne, 9–24. Palgrave Macmillan. 10.1007/978‑3‑030‑40168‑9_2
    https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-40168-9_2 [Google Scholar]
  11. 2020La giustificazione della decisione giudiziale. G. Giappichelli Editore.
    [Google Scholar]
  12. 2023 “Legislative Intentions and Counterfactuals: Or, What One Can Still Learn from Dworkin’s Critique of Legal Positivism.” Ratio Juris36(1):26–47. 10.1111/raju.12368
    https://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12368 [Google Scholar]
  13. Chiassoni, Pierluigi
    2019Interpretation without Truth. Berlin: Springer International Publishing. 10.1007/978‑3‑030‑15590‑2
    https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15590-2 [Google Scholar]
  14. Cohen, Mathilde
    2015 “When Judges Have Reasons Not to Give Reasons: A Comparative Law Approach.” Washington and Lee Law Review721:483–571.
    [Google Scholar]
  15. Comanducci, Paolo
    2021 ““Facciamo a capirci”: Conversazione ordinaria e interpretazione giuridica.” Lo stato: Rivista semestrale di scienza costituzionale, diritto dell’economia e teoria del diritto9(16):429–440.
    [Google Scholar]
  16. Danziger, Shai, Levav, Jonathan & Avnaim-Pesso, Liora
    2011 “Extraneous factors in judicial decisions.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America108(17):6889–6892. 10.1073/pnas.1018033108
    https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1018033108 [Google Scholar]
  17. Dworkin, Ronald
    1986Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  18. Erlanger, Howard, Garth, Bryant, Larson, Jane, Mertz, Elizabeth, Nourse, Victoria, Wilkins, David
    2005 “Is It Time for a New Legal Realism?” Wisconsin Law Review 2005:335–363.
    [Google Scholar]
  19. Eskridge Jr., William N.
    1989 “The New Textualism”. UCLA Law Review371621–691.
    [Google Scholar]
  20. Gabba, Carlo Francesco
    1884Le donne non avvocate. Pisa: Tipografia Nistri & C.
    [Google Scholar]
  21. Grove, Tara Leigh
    2023 “The Misunderstood History Of Textualism.” Northwestern University Law Review117(4):1–65.
    [Google Scholar]
  22. Hannikainen, IR, Tobia, KP, de Almeida, GDFCF, Struchiner, N, Kneer, M, Bystranowski, P, Dranseika, V, Strohmaier, N, Bensinger, S, Dolinina, K, Janik, B, Lauraitytė, E, Laakasuo, M, Liefgreen, A, Neiders, I, Próchnicki, M, Rosas, A, Sundvall, J & Żuradzki, T.
    2022 “Coordination and expertise foster legal textualism.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences119(44):1–8. 10.1073/pnas.2206531119
    https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2206531119 [Google Scholar]
  23. Iannuzzi, Ilaria and Pasquale Tammaro
    2022Lidia Poët. La Prima Avvocata, Milan: Le Lucerne.
    [Google Scholar]
  24. Krishnakumar, Anita S.
    2010 “Statutory Interpretation in the Roberts Court’s First Era: An Empirical and Doctrinal Analysis.” Hastings Law Journal621:221–296. 10.2139/ssrn.1503442
    https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1503442 [Google Scholar]
  25. Leiter, Brian
    1995 “Legal Indeterminacy.” Legal Theory1(4):481–492. 10.1017/S1352325200000227
    https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325200000227 [Google Scholar]
  26. 2010 “Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What is the Issue?” Legal Theory16(2):111–133. 10.1017/S1352325210000121
    https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325210000121 [Google Scholar]
  27. MacCormick, D. Neil & Robert S. Summers
    1991Interpreting Statutes. Routledge.
    [Google Scholar]
  28. Marghieri
    , Le donne avvocate, Napoli 1884.
    [Google Scholar]
  29. Matczak, Marcin
    2017 “Three Kinds of Intention in Lawmaking.” Law and Philosophy36(6):651–674. 10.1007/s10982‑017‑9302‑8
    https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-017-9302-8 [Google Scholar]
  30. Miles, Thomas J. & Sunstein, Cass R.
    2008 “The New Legal Realism.” The University of Chicago Law Review751:831–851
    [Google Scholar]
  31. Nourse, Victoria F.
    2012 “A Decision Theory of Statutory Interpretation.” The Yale Law Journal701:70–152.
    [Google Scholar]
  32. Nourse, Victoria F. & Shaffer, Gregory
    2016 “Varieties of New Legal Realism: Can a New World Order Prompt a New Legal Theory.” Cornell Law Review951:61–138.
    [Google Scholar]
  33. Poët, Lidia
    1883Ricorso all’Eccellentissima Corte d’Appello in data 14.11.1883, Turin: Stamperia dell’Unione Tipografico-Editrice
    [Google Scholar]
  34. Poggi, Francesca
    2013 “The Myth of Literal Meaning in Legal Interpretation.” Analisi e diritto3131–335.
    [Google Scholar]
  35. Ranelletti Eutimio
    Ranelletti Eutimio 1957La Donna giudice, ovverosia la “grazia” contro la “giustizia.”Milano: Giuffrè.
    [Google Scholar]
  36. Recanati, Francois
    2004Literal Meaning. Cambridge University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  37. Ricci, Cristina
    2022Lidia Poët. Vita e battaglie della prima avvocata italiana, pionieria dell’emancipazione femminile, Turin: Graphot.
    [Google Scholar]
  38. Rodriguez-Blanco, Veronica
    2013 “Claims of Legal Authorities and “Expressions of Intention”: The Limits of Philosophy of Language.” Law and Language, ed. byMichael Freeman & Fiona Smith, 79–99. Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199673667.003.0042
    https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199673667.003.0042 [Google Scholar]
  39. Sabatini, Alma
    1987 “Raccomandazioni per un uso non sessista della lingua Italiana.” Il Sessismo nella Lingua Italiana. ed. byAlma Sabatini, 95–122. Presidenza del Consiglio dei Ministri e Commissione Nazionale per la Parità e le Pari Opportunità tra uomo e donna.
    [Google Scholar]
  40. Sandro, Paolo
    2022The Making of Constitutional Democracy. Bloomsbury Publishing. 10.5040/9781509905249
    https://doi.org/10.5040/9781509905249 [Google Scholar]
  41. Scalia, Antonin & Garner, Brian A.
    2012Reading Law. Thompson/West.
    [Google Scholar]
  42. Schauer, Frederick
    1990 “Statutory Construction and the Coordinating Function of Plain Meaning.” The Supreme Court Review 1990:231–256. 10.1086/scr.1990.3109661
    https://doi.org/10.1086/scr.1990.3109661 [Google Scholar]
  43. 2015a “Is Law a Technical Language?” San Diego Law Review521:501–513.
    [Google Scholar]
  44. 2015b “On the Relationship Between Legal and Ordinary Language.” Speaking of Language and Law: Conversations on the Work of Peter Tiersma, ed. byLawrence Solan, Ainsworth, Janet & Roger W. Shuy, 35–38. Oxford University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  45. Skoczeń, Izabela
    2015 “Minimal Semantics and Legal Interpretation.” International Journal of Semiotics and Law29(3):615–633. 10.1007/s11196‑015‑9448‑3
    https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-015-9448-3 [Google Scholar]
  46. Slocum, Brian G.
    2015 “The Ordinary Meaning of Rules.” Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following. ed. byMichał Araszkiewicz, Paweł Banas, Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki & Krzysztof Płeszka. 295–317. Springer International Publishing. 10.1007/978‑3‑319‑09375‑8_22
    https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09375-8_22 [Google Scholar]
  47. 2016Ordinary Meaning. University of Chicago Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  48. Slocum, Brian G. & Wong Jarrod
    2021 “The Vienna Convention and Ordinary Meaning in International Law.” Yale Journal of International Law461:191–239.
    [Google Scholar]
  49. Solum, Lawrence B.
    2014 “Communicative Content and Legal Content.” Notre Dame Law Review891:479–520.
    [Google Scholar]
  50. Sommers, Roseanna
    2021 “Experimental jurisprudence.” Science3731:394–395. 10.1126/science.abf0711
    https://doi.org/10.1126/science.abf0711 [Google Scholar]
  51. Spaić, Bojan
    2017 “Institutional Control of Interpretation.” Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. ed. byMortimer Sellers & Stephan Kirste. 1–6. Springer Netherlands. 10.1007/978‑94‑007‑6730‑0_213‑1
    https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_213-1 [Google Scholar]
  52. 2018 “Normativity of Basic Rules of Legal Interpretation.” Unpacking Normativity. ed. byKenneth Einar Himma, Miodrag Jovanović & Bojan Spaić. 157–175. Hart Publishing. 10.5040/9781509916276.ch‑009
    https://doi.org/10.5040/9781509916276.ch-009 [Google Scholar]
  53. 2023 “Formalism.” In: Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. ed. byMortimer Sellers & Stephan Kirste. 1–8. Springer.
    [Google Scholar]
  54. Szabo, Zoltan Gendler
    2005Semantics Versus Pragmatics. Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251520.001.0001
    https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251520.001.0001 [Google Scholar]
  55. Thumma, Samuel A. & Kischmeier, Jeffrey L.
    1999 “The Lexicon Has Become a Fortress: The United States Supreme Court’s Use of Dictionaries.” Buffalo Law Review471:228–561.
    [Google Scholar]
  56. Tobia, Kevin P.
    2020 “Testing Ordinary Meaning.” Harvard Law Review1341:728–806.
    [Google Scholar]
  57. 2022 “Experimental Jurisprudence.” The University of Chicago Law Review891:735–802.
    [Google Scholar]
  58. Tobia, Kevin, Brian G. Slocum, and Victoria Nourse
    2023 “Ordinary Meaning and Ordinary People.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review1711365–458.
    [Google Scholar]
  59. Toulmin, Stephen E.
    2003The Uses of Argument. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511840005
    https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511840005 [Google Scholar]
  60. Viale, Chiara
    2022Lidia e le altre, Pari opportunità ieri e oggi: l’eredità di Lidia Poët. Milan: Guerini Next.
    [Google Scholar]
  61. Walton, Douglas, Macagno, Fabrizio & Sartor, Giovanni
    2021Statutory Interpretation. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/9781108554572
    https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108554572 [Google Scholar]
  62. Weisser, Martin
    2016Practical Corpus Linguistics: An Introduction to Corpus-Based Language Analysis. John Wiley & Sons. 10.1002/9781119180180
    https://doi.org/10.1002/9781119180180 [Google Scholar]
  63. Zoldan, Evan C.
    2019 “Corpus Linguistics and the Dream of Objectivity.” Seton Hall Law Review50 (2):401–448.
    [Google Scholar]
/content/journals/10.1075/jaic.00025.isi
Loading
This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was successful
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error