1887
Volume 1, Issue 2
  • ISSN 2772-3720
  • E-ISSN: 2772-3739
USD
Buy:$35.00 + Taxes

Abstract

Abstract

-clefts in English, their French and German counterparts and pre-verbal focus in Hungarian have been claimed to be semantically related constructions. For example, É. Kiss (1998) terms them and Destruel et al. (2015) coin them . Despite their similarities, these constructions also exhibit one major distributional difference: Clefts are usually no natural answers to overt -questions whereas pre-verbal focus in Hungarian constitutes the default question-answering strategy. In this paper, I show that it is possible to account for this difference within the Rational Speech Act model (Frank & Goodman 2012) without assuming any semantic differences between the structures. Thereby, I capitalize on the number of alternative constructions that could be used to answer overt -questions in the various languages under discussion and on a remarkable semantic property of the constructions under discussion that relates to the way they encode exhaustivity.

Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.1075/jul.00008.one
2022-11-17
2024-09-16
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

References

  1. Bende-Farkas, Ágnes
    2006Comparing English and Hungarian focus. Unpublished manuscript. IMS Stuttgart.
    [Google Scholar]
  2. Bergen, Leon & Noah D. Goodman
    2015 The strategic use of noise in pragmatic reasoning. Topics in Cognitive Science71. 336–350. 10.1111/tops.12144
    https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12144 [Google Scholar]
  3. Bergen, Leon, Roger Levy & Noah D. Goodman
    2016 Pragmatic reasoning through semantic inference. Semantics and Pragmatics91. 10.3765/sp.9.20ISSN: 1937-8912.
    https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.9.20 [Google Scholar]
  4. Büring, Daniel
    2010Conditional exhaustivity presuppositions in clefts (and definites). Ms. ZAS/Vienna.
    [Google Scholar]
  5. Büring, Daniel & Manuel Križ
    2013 It’s that, and that’s it! Exhaustivity and homogeneity presuppositions in clefts (and definites). Semantics and Pragmatics61. 1–29. 10.3765/sp.6.6
    https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.6.6 [Google Scholar]
  6. Cable, Seth
    2007 The grammar of Q: Q-particles and the nature of wh-fronting. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.
  7. Cinque, Guglielmo
    1993 A null-theory of phrase and compound stress. Linguistic Inquiry241. 239–267.
    [Google Scholar]
  8. Destruel, Emilie
    2016 Focus marking asymmetries in colloquial and standard French: a stochastic optimality-theoretic account. Journal of French Language Studies261. 299–326. 10.1017/S0959269515000265
    https://doi.org/10.1017/S0959269515000265 [Google Scholar]
  9. Destruel, Emilie, David I. Beaver & Elizabeth Coppock
    2019 It’s not what you expected. The surprising nature of cleft-alternatives in French and English. Frontiers in Psychology101. 1400. 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01400
    https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01400 [Google Scholar]
  10. Destruel, Emilie & Leah Velleman
    2014 Refining contrast: Empirical evidence from the English it-cleft. Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics101. 197–214.
    [Google Scholar]
  11. Destruel, Emilie, Daniel Velleman, Edgar Onea, Dylan Bumford, Jingyang Xue & David Beaver
    2015 A cross-linguistic study of the non-at-issueness of exhaustive inferences. InFlorian Schwarz (ed.), Experimental perspectives on presuppositions, 135–156. Heidelberg and Berlin: Springer. 10.1007/978‑3‑319‑07980‑6_6
    https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-07980-6_6 [Google Scholar]
  12. De Veaugh-Geiss, Joseph P., Swantje Tönnis, Edgar Onea & Malte Zimmermann
    2018 That’s not quite it: An experimental investigation of (non-)exhaustivity in clefts. Semantics and Pragmatics111. 1–44. 10.3765/sp.11.3
    https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.11.3 [Google Scholar]
  13. É. Kiss, Katalin
    1998 Identificational focus versus information focus. Language741. 245–273. 10.1353/lan.1998.0211
    https://doi.org/10.1353/lan.1998.0211 [Google Scholar]
  14. Féry, Caroline
    2013 Focus as prosodic alignment. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory311. 683–734. 10.1007/s11049‑013‑9195‑7
    https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-013-9195-7 [Google Scholar]
  15. Frank, Michael C. & Noah D. Goodman
    2012 Predicting pragmatic reasoning in language games. Science336 (6084). 998. 10.1126/science.1218633
    https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1218633 [Google Scholar]
  16. Gerőcs, Mátyás, Anna Babarczy & Balázs Surányi
    2014 Exhaustivity in focus: Experimental evidence from Hungarian. Language Use and Linguistic Structure31. 181–194. 10.5507/ff.14.24440606.13
    https://doi.org/10.5507/ff.14.24440606.13 [Google Scholar]
  17. Geurts, Bart & Rob van der Sandt
    2004 Interpreting focus. Theoretical Linguistics301. 1–44. 10.1515/thli.2004.005
    https://doi.org/10.1515/thli.2004.005 [Google Scholar]
  18. Horn, Laurence R.
    1981 Exhaustiveness and the semantics of clefts. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society141. 108–131.
    [Google Scholar]
  19. Kotek, Hadas
    2019Composing questions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/10774.001.0001
    https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/10774.001.0001 [Google Scholar]
  20. Lambrecht, Knud
    2000 When subjects behave like objects. Studies in Language241. 611–682. 10.1075/sl.24.3.06lam
    https://doi.org/10.1075/sl.24.3.06lam [Google Scholar]
  21. Onea, Edgar
    2019 Exhaustivity in it-clefts. InChris Cummins and Napoleon Katsos (eds.), The Oxford handbook of experimental semantics and pragmatics, 401–417. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198791768.013.17
    https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198791768.013.17 [Google Scholar]
  22. Pavlovic, Anna-Christina
    2019 The interpretation of it-clefts. PhD dissertation, Göttingen.
  23. Percus, Orin
    1997 Prying open the cleft. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society271. 337–351.
    [Google Scholar]
  24. Pollard, Carl & Murat Yasavul
    2014 Anaphoric it-clefts: The myth of exhaustivity. Proceedings of the 50th Annual Conference of the Chicago Linguistic Society.
    [Google Scholar]
  25. Roberts, Craige
    2012a Information structure: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics51. 1–57. 10.3765/sp.5.6
    https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.5.6 [Google Scholar]
  26. 2012b Information structure: Afterword. Semantics and Pragmatics51. 1–19. 10.3765/sp.5.7
    https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.5.7 [Google Scholar]
  27. Rooth, Mats
    1992 A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics11. 75–116. 10.1007/BF02342617
    https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02342617 [Google Scholar]
  28. Selkirk, Elizabeth
    1995 Sentence prosody: Intonation stress and phrasing. InJohn Goldsmith (ed.), Handbook of phonological theory, 550–569. Oxford: Blackwell.
    [Google Scholar]
  29. Skopeteas, Stavros & Gisbert Fanselow
    2010 Focus types and argument asymmetries. A cross-linguistic study in language production. InCarsten Breul & Edward Göbbel (ed.), Comparative and contrastive studies in information structure, 169–197. Amsterdam: Benjamins. 10.1075/la.165.07sko
    https://doi.org/10.1075/la.165.07sko [Google Scholar]
  30. 2011 Focus and the exclusion of alternatives: On the interaction of syntactic structure with pragmatic inference. Lingua1211. 1693–1706. 10.1016/j.lingua.2011.05.005
    https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2011.05.005 [Google Scholar]
  31. Spector, Benjamin
    2017 The pragmatics of plural predication: Homogeneity and non-maximality within the rational speech act model. InAlexandre Cremers, Thom van Gessel & Floris Roelofsen (eds.), Proceedings of the 21st Amsterdam colloquium, 435–444. Amsterdam.
    [Google Scholar]
  32. Stalnaker, Robert L.
    2002 Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy251. 701–721. 10.1023/A:1020867916902
    https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020867916902 [Google Scholar]
  33. Surányi, Balázs
    2011 A szintaktikailag jelöletlen fókusz pragmatikája. [The pragmatics of syntactically unmarked focus.] Általános Nyelvészeti Tanulmányok XXIII. [Studies in General Linguistics XXIII.] 281–313.
    [Google Scholar]
  34. Sutton, Richard S. & Andrew G. Barto
    1998Reinforcement learning. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  35. Szabolcsi, Anna
    1994 All quantifiers are not equal: The case of focus. Acta Linguistica Hungarica421. 171–187.
    [Google Scholar]
  36. Tönnis, Swantje, Lea M. Fricke & Alexander Schreiber
    2018 Methodological considerations on testing argument asymmetry in German cleft sentences. InEric Fuß, Marek Konopka, Beata Trawiński & Ulrich H. Waßner (eds.), Grammar and Corpora 2016, 231–240. Heidelberg: Heidelberg University Publishing.
    [Google Scholar]
  37. Velleman, Dan Bridges, David Beaver, Emilie Destruel, Dylan Bumford, Edgar Onea & Liz Coppock
    2012 It-clefts are IT (Inquiry Terminating) constructions. Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory221. 441–460. 10.3765/salt.v22i0.2640
    https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v22i0.2640 [Google Scholar]
  38. Wedgwood, Daniel
    2005Shifting the focus: From static structures to the dynamics of interpretation. Oxford: Elsevier. 10.1163/9780080457314
    https://doi.org/10.1163/9780080457314 [Google Scholar]
  39. Zimmermann, Malte, Joseph P. De Veaugh-Geiss, Swantje Tönnis & Edgar Onea
    2020 (Non-)Exhaustivity in focus partitioning across languages. InVeronika Hegedüs and Irene Vogel (eds.), Approaches to Hungarian. Vol.161, 207–230. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 10.1075/atoh.16.10zim
    https://doi.org/10.1075/atoh.16.10zim [Google Scholar]
/content/journals/10.1075/jul.00008.one
Loading
/content/journals/10.1075/jul.00008.one
Loading

Data & Media loading...

This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was successful
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error