1887
Volume 20, Issue 1
  • ISSN 1877-9751
  • E-ISSN: 1877-976X

Abstract

Abstract

If first-order empathy is the ability of Self to take into account Other’s point of view, then second-order empathy may be identified as the ability of Self to take into account Other’s point of view as including a view of Self. Considering that a hearer may choose between a first-order empathic and a second-order empathic interpretation of speaker utterances, second-order empathy introduces a pervasive indeterminacy in speaker-hearer interactions. The paper introduces this ambiguity potential in terms of the semiotics of face mask wearing during the corona pandemic, and then extrapolates the ensuing pattern of interpretative options to representative speech acts. The interaction between degree of empathy on one hand, and on the other the convergence or divergence of speaker and hearer beliefs is shown to yield six basic interpretative configurations: assertion, mistake, agreement, disagreement, irony, deception. Recognizing this ambiguity potential of second-order empathy is relevant for linguistic intersubjectivity research and post-Gricean pragmatics, and for the psychological theory of mind paradigm.

Available under the CC BY 4.0 license.
Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.1075/rcl.00101.gee
2022-05-24
2023-03-25
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

/deliver/fulltext/rcl.00101.gee.html?itemId=/content/journals/10.1075/rcl.00101.gee&mimeType=html&fmt=ahah

References

  1. Arslan, B., Taatgen, N. A., & Verbrugge, R.
    (2017) Five-year-olds’ systematic errors in second-order false belief tasks are due to first-order theory of mind strategy selection: A computational modeling study. Frontiers in Psychology, 8, 275. 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00275
    https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00275 [Google Scholar]
  2. Barnden, J.
    (2017) Irony, pretence and fictively-elaborating hyperbole. InA. Athanasiadou & H. L. Colston (Eds.), Irony in Language Use and Communication (pp.145–178). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins. 10.1075/ftl.1.08bar
    https://doi.org/10.1075/ftl.1.08bar [Google Scholar]
  3. Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A., & Frith, U.
    (1985) Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of mind’?Cognition, 21, 37–46. 10.1016/0010‑0277(85)90022‑8
    https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(85)90022-8 [Google Scholar]
  4. Clark, H. H., & Gerrig, R. J.
    (1984) On the pretense theory of irony. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 121–126. 10.1037/0096‑3445.113.1.121
    https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.113.1.121 [Google Scholar]
  5. Clark, H. H.
    (1996) Using language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511620539
    https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511620539 [Google Scholar]
  6. Corballis, M.
    (2014) The recursive mind: The origins of human language, thought, and civilization. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  7. Dunbar, R.
    (2000) On the origin of the human mind. InP. Carruthers (Ed.), Evolution and the human mind: Modularity, language and meta-cognition (pp.238–253). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511611926.012
    https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511611926.012 [Google Scholar]
  8. Geeraerts, D.
    (1989) Prospects and problems of prototype theory. Linguistics, 27, 587–612. 10.1515/ling.1989.27.4.587
    https://doi.org/10.1515/ling.1989.27.4.587 [Google Scholar]
  9. (1993) Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 223–272. 10.1515/cogl.1993.4.3.223
    https://doi.org/10.1515/cogl.1993.4.3.223 [Google Scholar]
  10. (2021) Second-order empathy, pragmatic ambiguity, and irony. InA. Soares da Silva (Ed.), Figures: Intersubjectivity and usage (pp.19–40). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins. 10.1075/ftl.11.01gee
    https://doi.org/10.1075/ftl.11.01gee [Google Scholar]
  11. Grice, H. P.
    (1957) Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388. 10.2307/2182440
    https://doi.org/10.2307/2182440 [Google Scholar]
  12. Grueneisen, S., Wyman, E., & Tomasello, M.
    (2015) “I know you don’t know I know…” Children use second-order false-belief reasoning for peer coordination. Child Development, 86, 287–293. 10.1111/cdev.12264
    https://doi.org/10.1111/cdev.12264 [Google Scholar]
  13. Kinderman, P., Dunbar, R., & Bentall, R. P.
    (1998) Theory-of-mind deficits and causal attributions. British Journal of Psychology, 89, 191–204. 10.1111/j.2044‑8295.1998.tb02680.x
    https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2044-8295.1998.tb02680.x [Google Scholar]
  14. Krebs, J. R., & Dawkins, R.
    (1984) Animal signals: Mind reading and manipulation. InJ. R. Krebs & N. B. Davies (Eds.), Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach (pp.380–402). Oxford: Blackwell.
    [Google Scholar]
  15. Meijering, B., van Rijn, H., Taatgen, N. A., & Verbrugge, R.
    (2011) I do know what you think I think: Second-order theory of mind in strategic games is not that difficult. Proceedings of the 33rd Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp.2486–2491).
    [Google Scholar]
  16. Miller, S. A.
    (2012) Theory of mind: Beyond the preschool years. New York: Psychology Press. 10.4324/9780203122730
    https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203122730 [Google Scholar]
  17. Morton, J.
    (1986) Developmental contingency modelling. A framework for discussing the processes of change and the consequence of deficiency. Advances in Psychology, 36, 141–165. 10.1016/S0166‑4115(09)60007‑8
    https://doi.org/10.1016/S0166-4115(09)60007-8 [Google Scholar]
  18. O’Grady, C., Kliesch, C., Smith, K., & Scott-Phillips, T. C.
    (2015) The ease and extent of recursive mindreading, across implicit and explicit tasks. Evolution and Human Behavior, 36, 313–322. 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.01.004
    https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.01.004 [Google Scholar]
  19. Premack, D., & Woodruff, G.
    (1978) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 515–526. 10.1017/S0140525X00076512
    https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00076512 [Google Scholar]
  20. Pylyshyn, Z. W.
    (1978) When is attribution of beliefs justified?Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 592–593. 10.1017/S0140525X00076895
    https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00076895 [Google Scholar]
  21. Sperber, D.
    (1984) Verbal irony: Pretense or echoic mention?Journal of Experimental Psychology, 113, 130–136. 10.1037/0096‑3445.113.1.130
    https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.113.1.130 [Google Scholar]
  22. (2000) Metarepresentations in an evolutionary perspective. InD. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: An interdisciplinary perspective (pp.117–137). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  23. Sperber, D., & Wilson, D.
    (1981) Irony and the use-mention distinction. InP. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp.295–318). New York: Academic Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  24. (1995) Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
    [Google Scholar]
  25. Tomasello, M.
    (2008) Origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/7551.001.0001
    https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/7551.001.0001 [Google Scholar]
  26. (2014) A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 10.4159/9780674726369
    https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674726369 [Google Scholar]
  27. Valle, A., Massaro, D., Castelli, I., & Marchettia, A.
    (2015) Theory of mind development in adolescence and early adulthood: The growing complexity of recursive thinking ability. Europe’s Journal of Psychology, 11, 112–124. 10.5964/ejop.v11i1.829
    https://doi.org/10.5964/ejop.v11i1.829 [Google Scholar]
  28. Verhagen, A.
    (2015) Grammar and cooperative communication. InE. Dąbrowska, & D. Divjak (Eds.), Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics (pp.232–252). Berlin & New York: De Gruyter Mouton. 10.1515/9783110292022‑012
    https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110292022-012 [Google Scholar]
  29. Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J.
    (2001) Meta-analysis of theory of mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development, 72, 655–684. 10.1111/1467‑8624.00304
    https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8624.00304 [Google Scholar]
  30. Wimmer, H., & Perner, J.
    (1983) Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103–128. 10.1016/0010‑0277(83)90004‑5
    https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(83)90004-5 [Google Scholar]
  31. Zlatev, J.
    (2008) The co-evolution of intersubjectivity and bodily mimesis. InJ. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp.215–244). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins. 10.1075/celcr.12.13zla
    https://doi.org/10.1075/celcr.12.13zla [Google Scholar]
http://instance.metastore.ingenta.com/content/journals/10.1075/rcl.00101.gee
Loading
/content/journals/10.1075/rcl.00101.gee
Loading

Data & Media loading...

This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was successful
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error